Why does the 'metric Lagrangian' approach appear to fail in Newtonian mechanics?Deriving the Lagrangian for a free particleLagrangian for relativistic massless point particleCurved spacetime point particle Lagrangian densityConfusion regarding the principle of least action in Landau & Lifshitz “The Classical Theory of Fields”Is there a Maupertuis principle for General Relativity?When the equations of motion are not unique (eg. when they are given by eigenvectors), which will the free particle adhere to?Physical motivation for Lagrangian formalismAre there arguments for the form of the Lagrangian in classical mechanics?Schwinger's variation of the action of point particle with *both* time and position as independent variablesDeriving the geodesic equation using a Lagrange multiplier to fix affine parametrisationWhy the Lagrangian of a free particle cannot depend on the position or time, explicitly?Confusing with the equation $(2.4)$ and $(2.5)$ of Landau and Lifshitz, Mechanics, Chapter 1, The principle of Least Action

Do empty drive bays need to be filled?

Most valuable information/technology for rebuilding after the apocalypse?

bash vs. zsh: What are the practical differences?

If the pressure inside and outside a balloon balance, then why does air leave when it pops?

Multiband vertical antenna not working as expected

Seasonality after 1st differencing

What do you call the action of "describing events as they happen" like sports anchors do?

What is Gilligan's full Name?

I've been given a project I can't complete, what should I do?

Assigning function to function pointer, const argument correctness?

Proving that a Russian cryptographic standard is too structured

Can I use 220v outlets on a 15 amp breaker and wire it up as 110v?

Why did Intel abandon unified CPU cache?

If there's something that implicates the president why is there then a national security issue? (John Dowd)

Find all letter Combinations of a Phone Number

Can you make an identity from this product?

Is there a DSLR/mirorless camera with minimal options like a classic, simple SLR?

Wizard clothing for warm weather

Is it safe to remove Python 2.7.15rc1 from Ubuntu 18.04?

Do you have to have figures when playing D&D?

What is the logic behind charging tax _in the form of money_ for owning property when the property does not produce money?

How can I remove material from this wood beam?

Housemarks (superimposed & combined letters, heraldry)

Convert only certain words to lowercase



Why does the 'metric Lagrangian' approach appear to fail in Newtonian mechanics?


Deriving the Lagrangian for a free particleLagrangian for relativistic massless point particleCurved spacetime point particle Lagrangian densityConfusion regarding the principle of least action in Landau & Lifshitz “The Classical Theory of Fields”Is there a Maupertuis principle for General Relativity?When the equations of motion are not unique (eg. when they are given by eigenvectors), which will the free particle adhere to?Physical motivation for Lagrangian formalismAre there arguments for the form of the Lagrangian in classical mechanics?Schwinger's variation of the action of point particle with *both* time and position as independent variablesDeriving the geodesic equation using a Lagrange multiplier to fix affine parametrisationWhy the Lagrangian of a free particle cannot depend on the position or time, explicitly?Confusing with the equation $(2.4)$ and $(2.5)$ of Landau and Lifshitz, Mechanics, Chapter 1, The principle of Least Action













9












$begingroup$


A well known derivation of the free-space Lagrangian in Special Relativity goes as follows:



  • The action $mathcalS$ is a functional of the path taken through
    configuration space, $mathbfq(lambda)$, where $lambda$ is the
    path parameter


  • The action can be thought of as the total 'cost' of this path through configuration space. The path which is chosen is the
    'cheapest' of these paths (i.e. the one which minimises the action)


  • 'Valid physics' can be retrieved by correctly assigning each point along the path a `cost', to do so we invoke a function called the Lagrangian, $mathcalL$, such that:

$$mathcalS[mathbfq] = int_lambda_1^lambda_2 mathcalL(mathbfq(lambda), dotmathbfq(lambda), lambda) mathrm d lambda tag1$$



  • The extremal $mathcalS$ is given when $mathcalL$ satisfies the Euler-Lagrange equations.


  • In free space (assumed to be homogeneous and isotropic), the `cost' of each point along the path cannot be determined by either the position along the path, or the position in configuration space, as this would violate our free-space assumptions.


  • The only determining factor that can be allowed to influence the total cost of each point in space is the infinitesimal path length at each point, up to a dimensional constant $alpha$. Therefore:
    $$ mathcalS[mathbfq] = alpha int_mathbfq mathrm d s tag2$$


  • Using $mathrm d s^2 = mathrm d t^2 - mathrm d mathbfx^2 $, this gives:
    $$ mathcalS[mathbfq] = alphaint sqrt1 - dotx^2 mathrm d ttag3$$

  • We choose $alpha = - m c^2$ as the simplest invariant quantity that has the correct dimensions. Therefore if our path parameter is the coordinate time $t$, we have:
    $$ mathcalL = - m c^2 sqrt1 - dotx^2 tag4$$

This proof is found in many different sources (probably most notably in Landau-Lifshitz Volume 2, Chapter 2). This idea generalises into General Relativity, where the free-space Lagrangian is:
$$ mathcalL propto sqrtg_mu nu dotx_mu dotx_nu tag5$$
However. If we try to insert the Newtonian Euclidean 3-metric, it seems that we don't get the expected result: $mathcalL = frac12 m v^2 $. If we insert the Euclidean metric into the Landau-Lifshitz general definition, we find:
$$ mathcalL propto |mathbfv| tag6$$
The equations of motion predicted by the normal Lagrangian are a statement of Newton's I axiom ($p = $ const in free space), but the result of this Lagrangian is:
$$ textsgn(v_i) = textconst tag7$$
This isn't wrong, but it clearly does not contain all the information we expect the Lagrangian to contain!



Why does this approach (which has such resounding success in the relativstic case!) fail so badly when applied to the (supposedly simpler) Newtonian case? I know that under certain circumstances we can square the Lagrangian and retain the same equations of motion, but those proofs all relied on affine parameters etc., which seems like overkill for a Newtonian mechanics problem.



Am I missing something obvious? It seems like it should be trivial to recover classical mechanics from this method, when it is so 'easy' to get relativstic mechanics from it....










share|cite|improve this question











$endgroup$
















    9












    $begingroup$


    A well known derivation of the free-space Lagrangian in Special Relativity goes as follows:



    • The action $mathcalS$ is a functional of the path taken through
      configuration space, $mathbfq(lambda)$, where $lambda$ is the
      path parameter


    • The action can be thought of as the total 'cost' of this path through configuration space. The path which is chosen is the
      'cheapest' of these paths (i.e. the one which minimises the action)


    • 'Valid physics' can be retrieved by correctly assigning each point along the path a `cost', to do so we invoke a function called the Lagrangian, $mathcalL$, such that:

    $$mathcalS[mathbfq] = int_lambda_1^lambda_2 mathcalL(mathbfq(lambda), dotmathbfq(lambda), lambda) mathrm d lambda tag1$$



    • The extremal $mathcalS$ is given when $mathcalL$ satisfies the Euler-Lagrange equations.


    • In free space (assumed to be homogeneous and isotropic), the `cost' of each point along the path cannot be determined by either the position along the path, or the position in configuration space, as this would violate our free-space assumptions.


    • The only determining factor that can be allowed to influence the total cost of each point in space is the infinitesimal path length at each point, up to a dimensional constant $alpha$. Therefore:
      $$ mathcalS[mathbfq] = alpha int_mathbfq mathrm d s tag2$$


    • Using $mathrm d s^2 = mathrm d t^2 - mathrm d mathbfx^2 $, this gives:
      $$ mathcalS[mathbfq] = alphaint sqrt1 - dotx^2 mathrm d ttag3$$

    • We choose $alpha = - m c^2$ as the simplest invariant quantity that has the correct dimensions. Therefore if our path parameter is the coordinate time $t$, we have:
      $$ mathcalL = - m c^2 sqrt1 - dotx^2 tag4$$

    This proof is found in many different sources (probably most notably in Landau-Lifshitz Volume 2, Chapter 2). This idea generalises into General Relativity, where the free-space Lagrangian is:
    $$ mathcalL propto sqrtg_mu nu dotx_mu dotx_nu tag5$$
    However. If we try to insert the Newtonian Euclidean 3-metric, it seems that we don't get the expected result: $mathcalL = frac12 m v^2 $. If we insert the Euclidean metric into the Landau-Lifshitz general definition, we find:
    $$ mathcalL propto |mathbfv| tag6$$
    The equations of motion predicted by the normal Lagrangian are a statement of Newton's I axiom ($p = $ const in free space), but the result of this Lagrangian is:
    $$ textsgn(v_i) = textconst tag7$$
    This isn't wrong, but it clearly does not contain all the information we expect the Lagrangian to contain!



    Why does this approach (which has such resounding success in the relativstic case!) fail so badly when applied to the (supposedly simpler) Newtonian case? I know that under certain circumstances we can square the Lagrangian and retain the same equations of motion, but those proofs all relied on affine parameters etc., which seems like overkill for a Newtonian mechanics problem.



    Am I missing something obvious? It seems like it should be trivial to recover classical mechanics from this method, when it is so 'easy' to get relativstic mechanics from it....










    share|cite|improve this question











    $endgroup$














      9












      9








      9


      5



      $begingroup$


      A well known derivation of the free-space Lagrangian in Special Relativity goes as follows:



      • The action $mathcalS$ is a functional of the path taken through
        configuration space, $mathbfq(lambda)$, where $lambda$ is the
        path parameter


      • The action can be thought of as the total 'cost' of this path through configuration space. The path which is chosen is the
        'cheapest' of these paths (i.e. the one which minimises the action)


      • 'Valid physics' can be retrieved by correctly assigning each point along the path a `cost', to do so we invoke a function called the Lagrangian, $mathcalL$, such that:

      $$mathcalS[mathbfq] = int_lambda_1^lambda_2 mathcalL(mathbfq(lambda), dotmathbfq(lambda), lambda) mathrm d lambda tag1$$



      • The extremal $mathcalS$ is given when $mathcalL$ satisfies the Euler-Lagrange equations.


      • In free space (assumed to be homogeneous and isotropic), the `cost' of each point along the path cannot be determined by either the position along the path, or the position in configuration space, as this would violate our free-space assumptions.


      • The only determining factor that can be allowed to influence the total cost of each point in space is the infinitesimal path length at each point, up to a dimensional constant $alpha$. Therefore:
        $$ mathcalS[mathbfq] = alpha int_mathbfq mathrm d s tag2$$


      • Using $mathrm d s^2 = mathrm d t^2 - mathrm d mathbfx^2 $, this gives:
        $$ mathcalS[mathbfq] = alphaint sqrt1 - dotx^2 mathrm d ttag3$$

      • We choose $alpha = - m c^2$ as the simplest invariant quantity that has the correct dimensions. Therefore if our path parameter is the coordinate time $t$, we have:
        $$ mathcalL = - m c^2 sqrt1 - dotx^2 tag4$$

      This proof is found in many different sources (probably most notably in Landau-Lifshitz Volume 2, Chapter 2). This idea generalises into General Relativity, where the free-space Lagrangian is:
      $$ mathcalL propto sqrtg_mu nu dotx_mu dotx_nu tag5$$
      However. If we try to insert the Newtonian Euclidean 3-metric, it seems that we don't get the expected result: $mathcalL = frac12 m v^2 $. If we insert the Euclidean metric into the Landau-Lifshitz general definition, we find:
      $$ mathcalL propto |mathbfv| tag6$$
      The equations of motion predicted by the normal Lagrangian are a statement of Newton's I axiom ($p = $ const in free space), but the result of this Lagrangian is:
      $$ textsgn(v_i) = textconst tag7$$
      This isn't wrong, but it clearly does not contain all the information we expect the Lagrangian to contain!



      Why does this approach (which has such resounding success in the relativstic case!) fail so badly when applied to the (supposedly simpler) Newtonian case? I know that under certain circumstances we can square the Lagrangian and retain the same equations of motion, but those proofs all relied on affine parameters etc., which seems like overkill for a Newtonian mechanics problem.



      Am I missing something obvious? It seems like it should be trivial to recover classical mechanics from this method, when it is so 'easy' to get relativstic mechanics from it....










      share|cite|improve this question











      $endgroup$




      A well known derivation of the free-space Lagrangian in Special Relativity goes as follows:



      • The action $mathcalS$ is a functional of the path taken through
        configuration space, $mathbfq(lambda)$, where $lambda$ is the
        path parameter


      • The action can be thought of as the total 'cost' of this path through configuration space. The path which is chosen is the
        'cheapest' of these paths (i.e. the one which minimises the action)


      • 'Valid physics' can be retrieved by correctly assigning each point along the path a `cost', to do so we invoke a function called the Lagrangian, $mathcalL$, such that:

      $$mathcalS[mathbfq] = int_lambda_1^lambda_2 mathcalL(mathbfq(lambda), dotmathbfq(lambda), lambda) mathrm d lambda tag1$$



      • The extremal $mathcalS$ is given when $mathcalL$ satisfies the Euler-Lagrange equations.


      • In free space (assumed to be homogeneous and isotropic), the `cost' of each point along the path cannot be determined by either the position along the path, or the position in configuration space, as this would violate our free-space assumptions.


      • The only determining factor that can be allowed to influence the total cost of each point in space is the infinitesimal path length at each point, up to a dimensional constant $alpha$. Therefore:
        $$ mathcalS[mathbfq] = alpha int_mathbfq mathrm d s tag2$$


      • Using $mathrm d s^2 = mathrm d t^2 - mathrm d mathbfx^2 $, this gives:
        $$ mathcalS[mathbfq] = alphaint sqrt1 - dotx^2 mathrm d ttag3$$

      • We choose $alpha = - m c^2$ as the simplest invariant quantity that has the correct dimensions. Therefore if our path parameter is the coordinate time $t$, we have:
        $$ mathcalL = - m c^2 sqrt1 - dotx^2 tag4$$

      This proof is found in many different sources (probably most notably in Landau-Lifshitz Volume 2, Chapter 2). This idea generalises into General Relativity, where the free-space Lagrangian is:
      $$ mathcalL propto sqrtg_mu nu dotx_mu dotx_nu tag5$$
      However. If we try to insert the Newtonian Euclidean 3-metric, it seems that we don't get the expected result: $mathcalL = frac12 m v^2 $. If we insert the Euclidean metric into the Landau-Lifshitz general definition, we find:
      $$ mathcalL propto |mathbfv| tag6$$
      The equations of motion predicted by the normal Lagrangian are a statement of Newton's I axiom ($p = $ const in free space), but the result of this Lagrangian is:
      $$ textsgn(v_i) = textconst tag7$$
      This isn't wrong, but it clearly does not contain all the information we expect the Lagrangian to contain!



      Why does this approach (which has such resounding success in the relativstic case!) fail so badly when applied to the (supposedly simpler) Newtonian case? I know that under certain circumstances we can square the Lagrangian and retain the same equations of motion, but those proofs all relied on affine parameters etc., which seems like overkill for a Newtonian mechanics problem.



      Am I missing something obvious? It seems like it should be trivial to recover classical mechanics from this method, when it is so 'easy' to get relativstic mechanics from it....







      special-relativity classical-mechanics lagrangian-formalism variational-principle action






      share|cite|improve this question















      share|cite|improve this question













      share|cite|improve this question




      share|cite|improve this question








      edited May 27 at 18:56







      almightyjack

















      asked May 26 at 11:15









      almightyjackalmightyjack

      464




      464




















          2 Answers
          2






          active

          oldest

          votes


















          12












          $begingroup$

          The problem with your approach is that your proposed action
          $$S = int |mathbfv| , dt$$
          is not invariant at all. While Landau's action is invariant under Lorentz transformations, and in fact completely coordinate independent, yours is not invariant under even Galilean transformations, which add a constant to $mathbfv$. The space-only analogue of a Lorentz transformation is not a Galilean transformation, it's a rotation. Your result is invariant under rotations, but that's not enough.



          Taking the nonrelativistic limit is not as simple as forgetting the time component. Parametrizing by time, the relativistic Lagrangian can also be written as
          $$mathcalL = sqrtdott^2 - dotmathbfx^2 = sqrt1 - mathbfv^2.$$
          We can arrive at your answer "getting rid of the one", but that's not the right way to take the limit. Instead the one becomes more important, and we have to keep it and Taylor expand about it, giving
          $$mathcalL approx 1 - fracmathbfv^22$$
          which recovers the usual nonrelativistic action. The argument for why we have to square $mathbfv$ is also given in volume 1 of Landau and Lifshitz. Perhaps a simpler way to say this is that Galilean physics isn't simply relativity with the time dimension removed.






          share|cite|improve this answer









          $endgroup$












          • $begingroup$
            I of course agree with the second half of your post (regarding the Taylor expansion), and I agree that my Lagrangian is not symmetric. However, I guess my real question is why that is the case. It seems obvious that the metric should encode all symmetries (i.e. the Minkowski metric encodes the Lorentz symmetries), so why doesn't the Euclidean metric encode the correct symmetries? What line element should one use if one were to derive pure classical physics from this same argument (i.e. not in the limit of relativity)
            $endgroup$
            – almightyjack
            May 26 at 12:51







          • 1




            $begingroup$
            @almightyjack Nonrelativistic physics naturally separates space and time, so what we usually call a metric there is just the spatial metric. If you did want a geometric formalism, you might want to look into Newton-Cartan theory, which has two metrics, one to measure spatial distance and one to measure times. I'm not sure if that'll lead directly to what you want, though.
            $endgroup$
            – knzhou
            May 26 at 12:59











          • $begingroup$
            thanks! This is something that's been bugging me for a long time. It feels like it should be addressed somewhere, as it is a very natural thing to do, when presented with the elegant L&L proof.... The 'correct' way I guess is to enforce Galilean invariance by hand (i.e. expand in powers of |v| and throw away any terms that are not total derivatives), but I just wanted to produce a more elegant analogue. I will let you know if Newton-Cartan theory gets me anywhere :)
            $endgroup$
            – almightyjack
            May 26 at 13:10










          • $begingroup$
            @knzhou : Or, effectively, that space and time "pull apart" in the limit as $c rightarrow infty$. Suggesting another interpretation of $c$: it's the "extent to which space and time mingle" (or better, of $frac1c$, which is also the per-distance minimum latency).
            $endgroup$
            – The_Sympathizer
            May 27 at 0:15



















          6












          $begingroup$

          1. A non-relativistic square root Lagrangian (6) has an issue with null-velocity vectors. It is not differentiable at zero velocity, which is unphysical from the perspective of Newtonian mechanics, cf. this related Phys.SE post.


          2. We should point out that the relativistic square root Lagrangian (5) has a similar shortcoming with null/lightlike vectors. It is only applicable to timelike vectors corresponding to massive point particles, cf. e.g. this Phys.SE post.






          share|cite|improve this answer











          $endgroup$













            Your Answer








            StackExchange.ready(function()
            var channelOptions =
            tags: "".split(" "),
            id: "151"
            ;
            initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

            StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function()
            // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
            if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled)
            StackExchange.using("snippets", function()
            createEditor();
            );

            else
            createEditor();

            );

            function createEditor()
            StackExchange.prepareEditor(
            heartbeatType: 'answer',
            autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
            convertImagesToLinks: false,
            noModals: true,
            showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
            reputationToPostImages: null,
            bindNavPrevention: true,
            postfix: "",
            imageUploader:
            brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
            contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
            allowUrls: true
            ,
            noCode: true, onDemand: true,
            discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
            ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
            );



            );













            draft saved

            draft discarded


















            StackExchange.ready(
            function ()
            StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fphysics.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f482512%2fwhy-does-the-metric-lagrangian-approach-appear-to-fail-in-newtonian-mechanics%23new-answer', 'question_page');

            );

            Post as a guest















            Required, but never shown

























            2 Answers
            2






            active

            oldest

            votes








            2 Answers
            2






            active

            oldest

            votes









            active

            oldest

            votes






            active

            oldest

            votes









            12












            $begingroup$

            The problem with your approach is that your proposed action
            $$S = int |mathbfv| , dt$$
            is not invariant at all. While Landau's action is invariant under Lorentz transformations, and in fact completely coordinate independent, yours is not invariant under even Galilean transformations, which add a constant to $mathbfv$. The space-only analogue of a Lorentz transformation is not a Galilean transformation, it's a rotation. Your result is invariant under rotations, but that's not enough.



            Taking the nonrelativistic limit is not as simple as forgetting the time component. Parametrizing by time, the relativistic Lagrangian can also be written as
            $$mathcalL = sqrtdott^2 - dotmathbfx^2 = sqrt1 - mathbfv^2.$$
            We can arrive at your answer "getting rid of the one", but that's not the right way to take the limit. Instead the one becomes more important, and we have to keep it and Taylor expand about it, giving
            $$mathcalL approx 1 - fracmathbfv^22$$
            which recovers the usual nonrelativistic action. The argument for why we have to square $mathbfv$ is also given in volume 1 of Landau and Lifshitz. Perhaps a simpler way to say this is that Galilean physics isn't simply relativity with the time dimension removed.






            share|cite|improve this answer









            $endgroup$












            • $begingroup$
              I of course agree with the second half of your post (regarding the Taylor expansion), and I agree that my Lagrangian is not symmetric. However, I guess my real question is why that is the case. It seems obvious that the metric should encode all symmetries (i.e. the Minkowski metric encodes the Lorentz symmetries), so why doesn't the Euclidean metric encode the correct symmetries? What line element should one use if one were to derive pure classical physics from this same argument (i.e. not in the limit of relativity)
              $endgroup$
              – almightyjack
              May 26 at 12:51







            • 1




              $begingroup$
              @almightyjack Nonrelativistic physics naturally separates space and time, so what we usually call a metric there is just the spatial metric. If you did want a geometric formalism, you might want to look into Newton-Cartan theory, which has two metrics, one to measure spatial distance and one to measure times. I'm not sure if that'll lead directly to what you want, though.
              $endgroup$
              – knzhou
              May 26 at 12:59











            • $begingroup$
              thanks! This is something that's been bugging me for a long time. It feels like it should be addressed somewhere, as it is a very natural thing to do, when presented with the elegant L&L proof.... The 'correct' way I guess is to enforce Galilean invariance by hand (i.e. expand in powers of |v| and throw away any terms that are not total derivatives), but I just wanted to produce a more elegant analogue. I will let you know if Newton-Cartan theory gets me anywhere :)
              $endgroup$
              – almightyjack
              May 26 at 13:10










            • $begingroup$
              @knzhou : Or, effectively, that space and time "pull apart" in the limit as $c rightarrow infty$. Suggesting another interpretation of $c$: it's the "extent to which space and time mingle" (or better, of $frac1c$, which is also the per-distance minimum latency).
              $endgroup$
              – The_Sympathizer
              May 27 at 0:15
















            12












            $begingroup$

            The problem with your approach is that your proposed action
            $$S = int |mathbfv| , dt$$
            is not invariant at all. While Landau's action is invariant under Lorentz transformations, and in fact completely coordinate independent, yours is not invariant under even Galilean transformations, which add a constant to $mathbfv$. The space-only analogue of a Lorentz transformation is not a Galilean transformation, it's a rotation. Your result is invariant under rotations, but that's not enough.



            Taking the nonrelativistic limit is not as simple as forgetting the time component. Parametrizing by time, the relativistic Lagrangian can also be written as
            $$mathcalL = sqrtdott^2 - dotmathbfx^2 = sqrt1 - mathbfv^2.$$
            We can arrive at your answer "getting rid of the one", but that's not the right way to take the limit. Instead the one becomes more important, and we have to keep it and Taylor expand about it, giving
            $$mathcalL approx 1 - fracmathbfv^22$$
            which recovers the usual nonrelativistic action. The argument for why we have to square $mathbfv$ is also given in volume 1 of Landau and Lifshitz. Perhaps a simpler way to say this is that Galilean physics isn't simply relativity with the time dimension removed.






            share|cite|improve this answer









            $endgroup$












            • $begingroup$
              I of course agree with the second half of your post (regarding the Taylor expansion), and I agree that my Lagrangian is not symmetric. However, I guess my real question is why that is the case. It seems obvious that the metric should encode all symmetries (i.e. the Minkowski metric encodes the Lorentz symmetries), so why doesn't the Euclidean metric encode the correct symmetries? What line element should one use if one were to derive pure classical physics from this same argument (i.e. not in the limit of relativity)
              $endgroup$
              – almightyjack
              May 26 at 12:51







            • 1




              $begingroup$
              @almightyjack Nonrelativistic physics naturally separates space and time, so what we usually call a metric there is just the spatial metric. If you did want a geometric formalism, you might want to look into Newton-Cartan theory, which has two metrics, one to measure spatial distance and one to measure times. I'm not sure if that'll lead directly to what you want, though.
              $endgroup$
              – knzhou
              May 26 at 12:59











            • $begingroup$
              thanks! This is something that's been bugging me for a long time. It feels like it should be addressed somewhere, as it is a very natural thing to do, when presented with the elegant L&L proof.... The 'correct' way I guess is to enforce Galilean invariance by hand (i.e. expand in powers of |v| and throw away any terms that are not total derivatives), but I just wanted to produce a more elegant analogue. I will let you know if Newton-Cartan theory gets me anywhere :)
              $endgroup$
              – almightyjack
              May 26 at 13:10










            • $begingroup$
              @knzhou : Or, effectively, that space and time "pull apart" in the limit as $c rightarrow infty$. Suggesting another interpretation of $c$: it's the "extent to which space and time mingle" (or better, of $frac1c$, which is also the per-distance minimum latency).
              $endgroup$
              – The_Sympathizer
              May 27 at 0:15














            12












            12








            12





            $begingroup$

            The problem with your approach is that your proposed action
            $$S = int |mathbfv| , dt$$
            is not invariant at all. While Landau's action is invariant under Lorentz transformations, and in fact completely coordinate independent, yours is not invariant under even Galilean transformations, which add a constant to $mathbfv$. The space-only analogue of a Lorentz transformation is not a Galilean transformation, it's a rotation. Your result is invariant under rotations, but that's not enough.



            Taking the nonrelativistic limit is not as simple as forgetting the time component. Parametrizing by time, the relativistic Lagrangian can also be written as
            $$mathcalL = sqrtdott^2 - dotmathbfx^2 = sqrt1 - mathbfv^2.$$
            We can arrive at your answer "getting rid of the one", but that's not the right way to take the limit. Instead the one becomes more important, and we have to keep it and Taylor expand about it, giving
            $$mathcalL approx 1 - fracmathbfv^22$$
            which recovers the usual nonrelativistic action. The argument for why we have to square $mathbfv$ is also given in volume 1 of Landau and Lifshitz. Perhaps a simpler way to say this is that Galilean physics isn't simply relativity with the time dimension removed.






            share|cite|improve this answer









            $endgroup$



            The problem with your approach is that your proposed action
            $$S = int |mathbfv| , dt$$
            is not invariant at all. While Landau's action is invariant under Lorentz transformations, and in fact completely coordinate independent, yours is not invariant under even Galilean transformations, which add a constant to $mathbfv$. The space-only analogue of a Lorentz transformation is not a Galilean transformation, it's a rotation. Your result is invariant under rotations, but that's not enough.



            Taking the nonrelativistic limit is not as simple as forgetting the time component. Parametrizing by time, the relativistic Lagrangian can also be written as
            $$mathcalL = sqrtdott^2 - dotmathbfx^2 = sqrt1 - mathbfv^2.$$
            We can arrive at your answer "getting rid of the one", but that's not the right way to take the limit. Instead the one becomes more important, and we have to keep it and Taylor expand about it, giving
            $$mathcalL approx 1 - fracmathbfv^22$$
            which recovers the usual nonrelativistic action. The argument for why we have to square $mathbfv$ is also given in volume 1 of Landau and Lifshitz. Perhaps a simpler way to say this is that Galilean physics isn't simply relativity with the time dimension removed.







            share|cite|improve this answer












            share|cite|improve this answer



            share|cite|improve this answer










            answered May 26 at 11:39









            knzhouknzhou

            50.5k12140246




            50.5k12140246











            • $begingroup$
              I of course agree with the second half of your post (regarding the Taylor expansion), and I agree that my Lagrangian is not symmetric. However, I guess my real question is why that is the case. It seems obvious that the metric should encode all symmetries (i.e. the Minkowski metric encodes the Lorentz symmetries), so why doesn't the Euclidean metric encode the correct symmetries? What line element should one use if one were to derive pure classical physics from this same argument (i.e. not in the limit of relativity)
              $endgroup$
              – almightyjack
              May 26 at 12:51







            • 1




              $begingroup$
              @almightyjack Nonrelativistic physics naturally separates space and time, so what we usually call a metric there is just the spatial metric. If you did want a geometric formalism, you might want to look into Newton-Cartan theory, which has two metrics, one to measure spatial distance and one to measure times. I'm not sure if that'll lead directly to what you want, though.
              $endgroup$
              – knzhou
              May 26 at 12:59











            • $begingroup$
              thanks! This is something that's been bugging me for a long time. It feels like it should be addressed somewhere, as it is a very natural thing to do, when presented with the elegant L&L proof.... The 'correct' way I guess is to enforce Galilean invariance by hand (i.e. expand in powers of |v| and throw away any terms that are not total derivatives), but I just wanted to produce a more elegant analogue. I will let you know if Newton-Cartan theory gets me anywhere :)
              $endgroup$
              – almightyjack
              May 26 at 13:10










            • $begingroup$
              @knzhou : Or, effectively, that space and time "pull apart" in the limit as $c rightarrow infty$. Suggesting another interpretation of $c$: it's the "extent to which space and time mingle" (or better, of $frac1c$, which is also the per-distance minimum latency).
              $endgroup$
              – The_Sympathizer
              May 27 at 0:15

















            • $begingroup$
              I of course agree with the second half of your post (regarding the Taylor expansion), and I agree that my Lagrangian is not symmetric. However, I guess my real question is why that is the case. It seems obvious that the metric should encode all symmetries (i.e. the Minkowski metric encodes the Lorentz symmetries), so why doesn't the Euclidean metric encode the correct symmetries? What line element should one use if one were to derive pure classical physics from this same argument (i.e. not in the limit of relativity)
              $endgroup$
              – almightyjack
              May 26 at 12:51







            • 1




              $begingroup$
              @almightyjack Nonrelativistic physics naturally separates space and time, so what we usually call a metric there is just the spatial metric. If you did want a geometric formalism, you might want to look into Newton-Cartan theory, which has two metrics, one to measure spatial distance and one to measure times. I'm not sure if that'll lead directly to what you want, though.
              $endgroup$
              – knzhou
              May 26 at 12:59











            • $begingroup$
              thanks! This is something that's been bugging me for a long time. It feels like it should be addressed somewhere, as it is a very natural thing to do, when presented with the elegant L&L proof.... The 'correct' way I guess is to enforce Galilean invariance by hand (i.e. expand in powers of |v| and throw away any terms that are not total derivatives), but I just wanted to produce a more elegant analogue. I will let you know if Newton-Cartan theory gets me anywhere :)
              $endgroup$
              – almightyjack
              May 26 at 13:10










            • $begingroup$
              @knzhou : Or, effectively, that space and time "pull apart" in the limit as $c rightarrow infty$. Suggesting another interpretation of $c$: it's the "extent to which space and time mingle" (or better, of $frac1c$, which is also the per-distance minimum latency).
              $endgroup$
              – The_Sympathizer
              May 27 at 0:15
















            $begingroup$
            I of course agree with the second half of your post (regarding the Taylor expansion), and I agree that my Lagrangian is not symmetric. However, I guess my real question is why that is the case. It seems obvious that the metric should encode all symmetries (i.e. the Minkowski metric encodes the Lorentz symmetries), so why doesn't the Euclidean metric encode the correct symmetries? What line element should one use if one were to derive pure classical physics from this same argument (i.e. not in the limit of relativity)
            $endgroup$
            – almightyjack
            May 26 at 12:51





            $begingroup$
            I of course agree with the second half of your post (regarding the Taylor expansion), and I agree that my Lagrangian is not symmetric. However, I guess my real question is why that is the case. It seems obvious that the metric should encode all symmetries (i.e. the Minkowski metric encodes the Lorentz symmetries), so why doesn't the Euclidean metric encode the correct symmetries? What line element should one use if one were to derive pure classical physics from this same argument (i.e. not in the limit of relativity)
            $endgroup$
            – almightyjack
            May 26 at 12:51





            1




            1




            $begingroup$
            @almightyjack Nonrelativistic physics naturally separates space and time, so what we usually call a metric there is just the spatial metric. If you did want a geometric formalism, you might want to look into Newton-Cartan theory, which has two metrics, one to measure spatial distance and one to measure times. I'm not sure if that'll lead directly to what you want, though.
            $endgroup$
            – knzhou
            May 26 at 12:59





            $begingroup$
            @almightyjack Nonrelativistic physics naturally separates space and time, so what we usually call a metric there is just the spatial metric. If you did want a geometric formalism, you might want to look into Newton-Cartan theory, which has two metrics, one to measure spatial distance and one to measure times. I'm not sure if that'll lead directly to what you want, though.
            $endgroup$
            – knzhou
            May 26 at 12:59













            $begingroup$
            thanks! This is something that's been bugging me for a long time. It feels like it should be addressed somewhere, as it is a very natural thing to do, when presented with the elegant L&L proof.... The 'correct' way I guess is to enforce Galilean invariance by hand (i.e. expand in powers of |v| and throw away any terms that are not total derivatives), but I just wanted to produce a more elegant analogue. I will let you know if Newton-Cartan theory gets me anywhere :)
            $endgroup$
            – almightyjack
            May 26 at 13:10




            $begingroup$
            thanks! This is something that's been bugging me for a long time. It feels like it should be addressed somewhere, as it is a very natural thing to do, when presented with the elegant L&L proof.... The 'correct' way I guess is to enforce Galilean invariance by hand (i.e. expand in powers of |v| and throw away any terms that are not total derivatives), but I just wanted to produce a more elegant analogue. I will let you know if Newton-Cartan theory gets me anywhere :)
            $endgroup$
            – almightyjack
            May 26 at 13:10












            $begingroup$
            @knzhou : Or, effectively, that space and time "pull apart" in the limit as $c rightarrow infty$. Suggesting another interpretation of $c$: it's the "extent to which space and time mingle" (or better, of $frac1c$, which is also the per-distance minimum latency).
            $endgroup$
            – The_Sympathizer
            May 27 at 0:15





            $begingroup$
            @knzhou : Or, effectively, that space and time "pull apart" in the limit as $c rightarrow infty$. Suggesting another interpretation of $c$: it's the "extent to which space and time mingle" (or better, of $frac1c$, which is also the per-distance minimum latency).
            $endgroup$
            – The_Sympathizer
            May 27 at 0:15












            6












            $begingroup$

            1. A non-relativistic square root Lagrangian (6) has an issue with null-velocity vectors. It is not differentiable at zero velocity, which is unphysical from the perspective of Newtonian mechanics, cf. this related Phys.SE post.


            2. We should point out that the relativistic square root Lagrangian (5) has a similar shortcoming with null/lightlike vectors. It is only applicable to timelike vectors corresponding to massive point particles, cf. e.g. this Phys.SE post.






            share|cite|improve this answer











            $endgroup$

















              6












              $begingroup$

              1. A non-relativistic square root Lagrangian (6) has an issue with null-velocity vectors. It is not differentiable at zero velocity, which is unphysical from the perspective of Newtonian mechanics, cf. this related Phys.SE post.


              2. We should point out that the relativistic square root Lagrangian (5) has a similar shortcoming with null/lightlike vectors. It is only applicable to timelike vectors corresponding to massive point particles, cf. e.g. this Phys.SE post.






              share|cite|improve this answer











              $endgroup$















                6












                6








                6





                $begingroup$

                1. A non-relativistic square root Lagrangian (6) has an issue with null-velocity vectors. It is not differentiable at zero velocity, which is unphysical from the perspective of Newtonian mechanics, cf. this related Phys.SE post.


                2. We should point out that the relativistic square root Lagrangian (5) has a similar shortcoming with null/lightlike vectors. It is only applicable to timelike vectors corresponding to massive point particles, cf. e.g. this Phys.SE post.






                share|cite|improve this answer











                $endgroup$



                1. A non-relativistic square root Lagrangian (6) has an issue with null-velocity vectors. It is not differentiable at zero velocity, which is unphysical from the perspective of Newtonian mechanics, cf. this related Phys.SE post.


                2. We should point out that the relativistic square root Lagrangian (5) has a similar shortcoming with null/lightlike vectors. It is only applicable to timelike vectors corresponding to massive point particles, cf. e.g. this Phys.SE post.







                share|cite|improve this answer














                share|cite|improve this answer



                share|cite|improve this answer








                edited May 26 at 21:35

























                answered May 26 at 12:24









                QmechanicQmechanic

                110k122081285




                110k122081285



























                    draft saved

                    draft discarded
















































                    Thanks for contributing an answer to Physics Stack Exchange!


                    • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

                    But avoid


                    • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

                    • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.

                    Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


                    To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




                    draft saved


                    draft discarded














                    StackExchange.ready(
                    function ()
                    StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fphysics.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f482512%2fwhy-does-the-metric-lagrangian-approach-appear-to-fail-in-newtonian-mechanics%23new-answer', 'question_page');

                    );

                    Post as a guest















                    Required, but never shown





















































                    Required, but never shown














                    Required, but never shown












                    Required, but never shown







                    Required, but never shown

































                    Required, but never shown














                    Required, but never shown












                    Required, but never shown







                    Required, but never shown







                    Popular posts from this blog

                    Wikipedia:Vital articles Мазмуну Biography - Өмүр баян Philosophy and psychology - Философия жана психология Religion - Дин Social sciences - Коомдук илимдер Language and literature - Тил жана адабият Science - Илим Technology - Технология Arts and recreation - Искусство жана эс алуу History and geography - Тарых жана география Навигация менюсу

                    Bruxelas-Capital Índice Historia | Composición | Situación lingüística | Clima | Cidades irmandadas | Notas | Véxase tamén | Menú de navegacióneO uso das linguas en Bruxelas e a situación do neerlandés"Rexión de Bruxelas Capital"o orixinalSitio da rexiónPáxina de Bruselas no sitio da Oficina de Promoción Turística de Valonia e BruxelasMapa Interactivo da Rexión de Bruxelas-CapitaleeWorldCat332144929079854441105155190212ID28008674080552-90000 0001 0666 3698n94104302ID540940339365017018237

                    What should I write in an apology letter, since I have decided not to join a company after accepting an offer letterShould I keep looking after accepting a job offer?What should I do when I've been verbally told I would get an offer letter, but still haven't gotten one after 4 weeks?Do I accept an offer from a company that I am not likely to join?New job hasn't confirmed starting date and I want to give current employer as much notice as possibleHow should I address my manager in my resignation letter?HR delayed background verification, now jobless as resignedNo email communication after accepting a formal written offer. How should I phrase the call?What should I do if after receiving a verbal offer letter I am informed that my written job offer is put on hold due to some internal issues?Should I inform the current employer that I am about to resign within 1-2 weeks since I have signed the offer letter and waiting for visa?What company will do, if I send their offer letter to another company